What connects modernity to the future? What does the future tell us about
modernity? What relation is there
between modernity and the future? The
more I stare at the word modernity,
the more I realize that the modern world is only beginning to come into
focus. High Modernism may have passed in
the 1930s, but modernity – and its aesthetic counterpart, modernism – is alive
and well. So what does it care about the
future?
In a fantastic novel by Richard Powers, Three Farmers on Their Way to a Dance, the
narrator conceptualizes something he calls “trigger points”:
As
with free-falling bodies, it seems apparent that such quickening change,
whether evolutionary, cultural, or technical, cannot accelerate indefinitely
but must reach some terminal velocity.
Call that terminal velocity a trigger point, where the rate of change of
the system reaches such a level that the system’s underpinning, its ability to
change, is changed. Trigger points come
about when the progress of a system becomes so accelerated, its tools become so
adept as self-replicating and self-modifying, that it thrusts an awareness of
itself onto itself and reaches the terminal velocity of self-reflection.
(Powers 81)
Something is coming to
consciousness in this description by Powers.
Complex systems are achieving a state, or level, at which their inner
workings become self-sufficient and, in the process, become reflexive in a way
that allows them to represent themselves back to themselves. They acquire the ability to conceive of
themselves as a system, along with the capacity to critique their own
composition. At this point, Powers
claims, the system reaches a point of critical mass, beyond which it cannot
evolve.
Three Farmers on
Their Way to a Dance, which covers three narratives strands from the early
1900s to the contemporary 1980s (the novel was published in 1985), identifies
here the moment of modernity itself.
That is, the moment at which history objectifies itself and thus
fragments itself. To put it in
psychoanalytic terms, the subject is split, Lacan’s $ (coincidentally also the
sign of the dollar, the ultimate alienating symbol of modernity). History, at this moment, also becomes “about
history,” as Powers puts it: “the century has become about itself, history about history: a still, eclectic, universally
reflexive, uniformly diverse, closed circle, the homogeneous debris in space
following a nova” (83). The self-divided
whole organizes itself, in Powers’s terminology, around what will eventually
become a singularity, or perhaps already is.
The nova – a phenomenon that occurs when a star collapses and builds an
accretion disc of matter and gases – is fated to become a gravitational
singularity, but Powers means it in a metaphorical sense, as a figure of
representation. Here we have to enter
into the tricky business of keeping the figurative constructions separate from
their objective correlates, and in order to do this I choose to employ that
ever feisty device: the dialectic.
In recent decades, the dialectic has become an increasingly
controversial term, drawing criticism from new Right conservative philosophers,[1]
new Left speculative philosophers,[2]
and even from its once loyal bedfellow, literary studies.[3] To invoke dialectics often means to conjure
the specters of Hegel and Marx, along with their two late 20th-century
innovators: Fredric Jameson and Slavoj Žižek.
Despite the recent skepticism toward dialectical methods of analysis, I
insist on their presence in this piece and elsewhere for one primary reason:
dialectical thought remains the most convincing and challenging conceptual form
for representing our reality to this day.
Aside from dissolving the subject entirely – even admitting its
existence as an illusion, a mental construction that emerges from brain
activity – there exists a fundamental correlation between the external world
and the world as perceived by human individuals. This is not to say that the external world
does not exist except in our perceptions; rather, it is to emphasize that we
remain beholden to our empirical observations of the world, even if these
observations are executed by instruments of modern technology. The closest we may come to thinking the
external world in-itself is the
epistemology of posthumanism; coincidentally, the emergent epistemology of
modernism itself.[4]
The dialectic does not propose to grant access to
objective reality. Furthermore, the
dialectic (as I deploy it here) does not threaten to hermetically seal us off
from objective reality entirely, leaving us blind to the external world. Rather, the dialectic must be recognized as
the privileged form of representation which simultaneously constructs, and
exposes the fragility of, the human subject as it exists in reality. Powers’s “trigger points,” demonstrate the
coming-to-consciousness of the modern world, but they also purport to establish
a conceptual and ontological boundary beyond which knowledge no longer
develops. The boundary casts
consciousness retrospectively onto the system that gives rise to it, but no
longer constitutes the (preconscious) acquisitive expansion of material
information. Instead, the subject that
emerges out of the system must conceive of itself dialectically in relation to
that which exists (ideally) beyond the point of terminal velocity.
This is how Powers arrives at the image of the nova,
which will eventually become a black hole.
In terms of the physics of the universe, black holes are not only
epistemologically unavailable to us; silent objects in dark rooms which would
become luminescent if we could simply turn on the light. They are, based on the very forms (space and
time) that human beings require for knowledge, ontologically unknowable.
They are physical implosions of space and time, anomalies that warp the
material universe immediately surrounding them (and likely, judging from their
apparent ubiquity in the universe, they exert considerable force on physical
reality as a whole). Powers’s choices to
describe the development of modernity, of history itself, as the matter
orbiting a nova, and as a series of
trigger points reaching terminal velocity, express a dialectical concern over historiography.
On the one hand, the novel attempts a cohesive
representation of history by tying its third-person narratives together through
the central motif of the eponymous photograph taken by August Sander; the
first-person narrative, in the voice of “Mr. P”, comments on the impact of
photography and other technological media, and offers some speculations on the
nature of history. On the other hand,
the novel disrupts this attempt, failing to draw together any ultimately
meaningful narrative. In fact, the
novel’s conclusion is almost deflationary; Peter Mays, after having discovered
his inheritance of a large sum of money from his ancestors, subsequently learns
that it is worth almost nothing due to inflation. Its most obvious narrative strand thus loses
all steam, coming depressingly to an abrupt and nearly inconsequential halt.
The text reflects what Powers defines as hyperprogress:
“Hyperprogress transmutes, paradoxically, into stillness. It is still
true that things have changed more in the last thirty years than in all the
time since Christ. Since it is still true, then nothing has changed since Peguy.
Social culture has taken tail in mouth and rolled a benzene ring” (83). What appears as progress exposes itself as
meaningless, valueless development; but this does not mean that the ideal of
progress – the object of desire – disappears.
Powers identifies the tendency of modern history to disguise itself as
progress while being nothing more than senseless accretion, as the matter
surrounding a nova; the Benjaminian storm that rages against the Angel of
History. The fantasy that is a
progressive society constructs an imaginary ideal – an image of cultural
improvement and/or perfection – and conceives of itself as striving toward this
ideal. However, history never achieves
this ideal, but can only ever approach it as a curve approaches an asymptote:
“Change in these fields [of science] does not stop at a trigger point. Only the curve of progress reaches a critical
moment, the second derivative goes to zero, and a new curve begins, pushed
forward into a new country” (82). Powers
conceives of history in an asymptotic fashion.
Fredric Jameson, recounting Derrida’s reading of Hegel, expresses
the French philosopher’s latent dialectical conclusion. Derrida, Jameson notes, declares that the
Hegelian Aufhebung is “not an event,
but a repetition”: “Nothing happens; all Aufhebung
are the same. They all seem to involve
the transcendence of nature; yet the latter is merely a name for whatever is
transcended in any of these processes, it is purely formal, the name of a
moment, it has no content in its own right” (“Hegel’s Critics” 105). Jameson moves deftly from poststructuralist
to poststructuralist, explicating Derrida’s, and then Deleuze’s, critique of
Hegelian Aufhebung; but the
emptiness, or ideal figuration, of Aufhebung
lurks as a constant specter (to invoke Derrida’s own terminology) in the
background of his analysis.[5] What emerges in Jameson’s intense study of
Derrida’s and Deleuze’s critiques of Hegel is the understanding of Aufhebung not as material development,
but as a representation of what matter develops toward.
This representation, as Jameson declares, is purely
ideological (106). Powers confirms as
much when he totalizes it as a modern synthetic image: “Nothing can take place
in this century without some coincident event linking it into a conspiratorial
whole” (Powers 83).[6] The reflexivity of history – its
self-awareness – does not give birth to some genuinely metaphysical, or
essential, notion of history that is at work in the world. Reflexivity results in the image, or the figure; above all else, the representation. History appears on the horizon as something
predestined or predetermined, as a course of necessary progression; but at the
same moment that it appears as such, it also undermines its necessity. It gives rise to the “conspiratorial whole” but
emphasizes that this whole is purely figural.
It does not subsist in reality; but it shapes our relationship to
reality because it is the only way in which we can conceive of this
relationship. And in this sense, the
representation of reality confronts reality itself dialectically. It is true
that we cannot know the in-itself;
but this does not dissipate the in-itself
into nothing more than a cognitive illusion.
That which escapes our representation, but which does not
dissipate, is epitomized by the mathematical (and, I’m inclined to say,
ontological) existence of the gravitational singularity; and this material
singularity shapes and constructs all other theoretical singularities. That which Aufhebung purports to represent – the historical singularity, the
virtual space of all possible historical trajectories – is unavailable to us as
human subjects. We can only ever
approximate the historical singularity through representation, which nears the
asymptote of the singularity but can never surpass it. The asymptote, in this conception, is
equivalent to the black hole’s event
horizon,[7]
beyond which no matter (not even light) can escape the black hole’s gravity,
thus making the black hole epistemologically and ontologically unavailable to
us as observers. We organize time into
linear constructs, and space into geographic mappings; but black holes break
down space and time, organizing an accretion disc of matter around the physical
implosion of space-time. Analogically,
the historical singularity (represented through the image of Aufhebung) organizes time around
perpetually collapsing matter: Benjamin’s Angel of History protesting the
encroaching storm of progress.
The “black hole,” the mathematical evidence for the
gravitational singularity (according to which there exists a supermassive black
hole at the center of most, if not all, galaxies), forms in our minds but
remains unrepresentable except through its unrepresentability. It is dark, lightless and soundless
(empirically absent), because it deconstructs the forms by which human subjects
can know – Kantian space and time.
Similarly, the historical singularity forms in our minds only through
the idealistic and ideological representations of Aufhebung; but the actuality of what we might term history – what
others have termed “deep time” or cosmic time[8] –
exists beyond notions of linear time and geological space. The event horizon of the historical
singularity is insurmountable according to the Kantian forms of space and time,
remains insurmountable even by our technological instruments. We can only approach it on an increasingly
shallow curve, representing it to ourselves as that which we approach in hopes
of achieving, as Don DeLillo describes in his novel, Point Omega: “‘The omega point,’ [Elster] said. ‘Whatever the intended meaning of this term,
if it has a meaning, if it’s not a case of language that’s struggling toward
some idea outside our experience’” (72).
DeLillo brings us even closer to the gravitational
singularity than Powers. As a
singularity that organized matter around collapsing spatiotemporal reality, the
black hole reflects our inconsequential materiality back to us: “‘We want to be
the dead matter we used to be. We’re the
last billionth of a second in the evolution of matter’” (50). Recalling the Freudian death drive, Thanatos, DeLillo echoes Deleuze’s (and
Nick Land’s) transplantation of the death drive into matter itself. We all orbit black holes, subjective
accretion discs, preparing for inevitable spatiotemporal implosion. The construct “human” exposes itself as
merely one more idealism: “‘De we have to be human forever? Consciousness is exhausted. Back now to inorganic matter. This is what we want. We want to be stones in a field’” (53). Forget time, forget space; eventually,
neither will be ours to remember.
There is one important difference to illuminate between
the historical and gravitational singularity.
The historical singularity exists, as does the gravitational, beyond the
standard form of time. We cannot
traverse the singularity’s event horizon because beyond this limit we would
descend into multi-dimensional time, into virtual
time. However, the event horizon of the
historical singularity is still an ideal construct;
if Aufhebung represents the
unachievable, but remains an ideal, then the line of demarcation also remains
ideal. We can never cross the event
horizon of Time because we have sealed ourselves off epistemologically,
experientally.
But you, I, we,
can all traverse the event horizon of a black hole.
The black hole is epistemologically and ontologically unavailable for the primary reason that to access
it literally equals death. We cannot know it, in our forms of space and
time; and we cannot access it because of these same forms, but also because the
black hole is a monster that eats us.
Eats everything; it eats space, time, gas, sound, light, the matter of
universal reality collapses in the gravitational anomaly. Human bodies are broken down, halved
infinitesimally, until nothing more than the subatomic particles that comprise
them (if not less…). Black holes are the
ontological instantiation of the material universe – reality, the real – that remains inaccessible for
human knowledge. Thus, if we maintain
the analogy, we must ask ourselves a daring question:
Is the historical singularity – which we represent to
ourselves via the peaceful, utopian, desirable
figure of Aufhebung – also that which
is only available to matter itself;
to the non-conscious? To the ground
known to Wordsworth’s Lucy?
No motion has she
now, no force;
She neither hears nor sees;
Roll’d round in earth’s diurnal
course,
With rocks, and stones, and trees.
What connects modernity
to the future? I would venture that it
is this very quality of modernity by which it turns its objectifying lens onto itself,
and thus relates itself representationally to the future it desires to achieve.[9] Futurity, closely aligned with the concept of
historical singularity, must exist in a virtual sense in that it possesses an
openness; but we must impose on it the representation of Aufhebung. That is, we must
narrow our scope so that we accommodate the Kantian impositions of space and
time. Futurity, as it actually exists –
the dark reality that wells up around our ankles – would kill us, consume
us. The dialectic thus serves two
purposes: it protects us from the spatiotemporal apocalypse that awaits us beyond the event horizon; and it provides
us with the form by which we can
simultaneously understand and critique our own relation to the world.
What Derrida perhaps unconsciously realized – and what
Jameson certainly realizes – is that the dialectic is its own critique; its own
deconstruction. The dialectic does not
destroy reality or seal us off entirely from it. The dialectic is the self-refuting form of our relationship to reality.
[2]
The new movement known as Speculative Realism has demonstrated considerable
resistance to dialectical thought.
[3]
For an example, see Susan Stanford Friedman’s criticism of Jameson in
“Planetarity: Musing Modernist Studies.”
Friedman accuses Jameson of a “reductionist” view that results in
“singularity”; namely, the reduction of modernism to the effect of global capitalism. In opposition to Friedman’s argument, and
building on Jameson’s, this essay contests the following: a) the emergent “singularity”
produced by dialectics is not interior to dialectics, and b) the dialectic is
not dismissive to that which is exterior.
[4]
This paper resists Quentin Meillassoux’s daring circumvention of all
post-Kantian “correlationist” philosophy, as argued in After Finitude: an Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. Meillassoux’s compelling argument about the
possibility to think a world without thought – for the object of thought to be
non-thought – provides a momentous and exciting departure from the tradition of
Western philosophy. However, the threat
(if we may call it such) of human extinction, and its ramifications on thought,
are broached already in 1987 by Jean-François Lyotard in book, The Inhuman, in a poststructuralist
manner quite different from Meillassoux’s method. Without succumbing entirely to Lyotard’s
postmodern pessimism, I venture a via
media that allows the dialectic to persist, but to accommodate the
possibility of thinking the non-thought.
The following pages will lay out a preliminary argument for such a
possibility.
[5]
The title of the section in which the essay is included is ‘Hegel Without Aufhebung’.
[6]
See the first essay in Jameson’s Postmodernism:
the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism for commentary on the ideological
structure of conspiracy theories.
[7] I
am tempted here to invoke Alain Badiou’s concept of the event; a common philosophical concept, but one that Badiou
conceives of as blasting the finitude of the State beyond its inherent
limitations (see Badiou’s brief essay “The Idea of Communism” in the
eponymously titled collection. This
language recalls Benjamin’s Messianic force of blasting history open in his Theses on the Philosophy of History.
[8]
See Stephen Jay Gould’s Time’s Arrow,
Time’s Cycle and Quentin Meillassoux’s After
Finitude (respectively).
[9]
One must be careful with psychoanalytic language lest one imposes a
psychoanalytic reading onto an objective ethos, a Weltanschauung; but if Aufhebung
is an ideological construct – that is, a fantasy
– then psychoanalysis has something to offer, to an extent. At the moment, all I will say is that if we
maintain the Freudian/Lacanian structuralism of a subject that desires and an
object of desire, then we can read our historical narrative accordingly: that
is, that history only appears retrospectively, that its object is imaginary
(and thus unattainable) but that it is simultaneously “written” by the object
that it pursues. The fantasy, as Žižek tells
us, actively constructs our reality.
Jameson unveils a very similar theory of history in The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act.